[Search Blog Here. Index-tags are found on the bottom of the left column.]
[Central Entry Directory]
[Leibniz Entry Directory]
[Calculus Entry Directory]
Straight line AX
and straight line EY
meet at point C
Straight line e forms between E and A, and it is perpendicular to AX.
Likewise, line y forms between X and Y, and it is also perpendicular to AX.
Lines e and y are parallel, because they are perpendicular to the same line.
Line AC is called c,
And all of line AX is called x
(x - c) / y = c / e
But now it can be rendered:
x / y = c / e
Because now, x - c = x; for c no longer has a finite extensive value to take from x, even though its relation to e still may be represented as
x / y.
So e and c are not nothing, because they preserve the ratio of CX to XY.
Leibniz also says that the ratio of the infinitely small c to e preserves the ratio of the radius and tangent of the angle at C, which would be the same as x and y:
So we know that c and e do not have extensive finite values, but we also know that they are not nothing. For, if they both equaled zero, then x / y would equal 0 / 0, which equals 1 [0r 1/1]. Hence in that case, x and y would have the same value, and thus x would equal y. However, this is absurd, because it could only be so if C's angle were 45-degrees. But we began by presuming that it was not.
So c and e are not taken to be zero, except in their relation to x and y. But when they are in a ratio to each other, c and e have an algebraic relation to one another.
And so they are treated as infinitesimals, exactly as are the elements which our differential calculus recognizes in the ordinates of curves for momentary increments and decrements.
(545d)
Although some reject the notion of the infinitesimal, it proves advantageous in solving certain algebraic problems that otherwise would be insoluble. As well in physics this principle may take the form of Leibniz's Law of Continuity, by which one may regard
equality as a particular case of inequality, rest as a special case of motion, parallelism as a case of convergence, etc., assuming not that the difference of magnitudes which become equal is already zero but that it is in the act of vanishing; and similarly in the case of motion, not that it is already zero in an absolute sense but that it is on the point of becoming zero.
(546b)
This sort of method was used by Archimedes; and anyone who criticized his use of infinitely small values would yet be unable to show how we may designate some magnitude for them.
Thus,
rest, equality, and the circle terminate the motions, the inequalities, and the regular polygons which arrive at them by a continuous change and vanish in them. And although these terminations are excluded, that is, are not included in any rigorous sense in the variables which they limit, they nevertheless have the same properties as if they were included in the series, in accordance with the language of infinites and infinitesimals, which takes the circle, for example, as a regular polygon with an infinite number of sides. Otherwise the law of continuity would be violated, namely, that since we can move from polygons to a circle by a continuous change and without making a leap, it is also necessary not to make a leap in passing from the properties of polygons to those of a circle.
(546c.d)
Hi, I would like to know if it possible to find the same justificacion for the differentiation rules, by regular geometry and by arithmetic.
ReplyDeleteHello,
ReplyDeleteDo you know where I will be able to access the paper you referenced, "Justification"? Thanks!