My Academia.edu Page w/ Publications

30 Mar 2015

Somers-Hall, (1.9), Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition, ‘1.9 Hegel (44–6/54–6, 51–3/62–4)’, summary


by
Corry Shores
[Search Blog Here. Index-tags are found on the bottom of the left column.]

[Central Entry Directory]
[Deleuze Entry Directory]
[Henry Somers-Hall, Entry Directory]
[Henry Somers-Hall’s Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition, Entry Directory]

 

[The following is summary. All boldface, underlining, and bracketed commentary are my own. Proofreading is incomplete, so please forgive my typos and other distracting mistakes. Somers-Hall is abbreviated SH.]



Summary of


Henry Somers-Hall


Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition:
An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide


Part 1
A Guide to the Text

 

Chapter 1. Difference in Itself

1.9 Hegel (44–6/54–6, 51–3/62–4)





Brief summary:

Hegel’s dialectic is an infinite movement. But it also generates the categories we use in representational thinking. Therefore, it is infinite representation, unlike the finite representation of Aristotle, which fixes things in a stable system of definitional limits. Nonetheless, 1) Hegel’s infinite representation still has a pattern-instance structure similar to Aristotle’s genus-species structure, 2) it makes no room for the uniqueness and singularity of each moment, since each in a sense is contained in or born out of prior states, and 3) the real world is too complicated and full of ambiguity to admit of Hegel’s system of cleanly distinct opposites.

 



Summary


[We previously made a general and brief distinction between finite and infinite representation.] Now we will begin by looking at two ways of putting the infinite representational approach into practice (44), namely, 1) Hegel’s synthetic approach, and 2) Leibniz’ manner of seeing “objects as fully defined by an infinite number of properties, thus making truths about them analytic” (44). [Perhaps the distinction here is something like the following. For Leibniz, objects from the beginning possess all their predicates, but there are infinitely many. So things still have a subject-predicate representational structure, but it is infinite. Hegel maybe would see things as part of a developmental movement by which they progressively obtain newer predications or traits or maybe substantialities, but infinitely so. Aristotle’s method of finitely fixing to things sets of properties without taking into account their development is what presents his problems, in Hegel’s view. The real totality is not all that is but rather the entirety of the movement which develops all that is in this motion of infinite becoming.]

In the case of Hegel, therefore, this means that the kind of thinking which has characterised representation so far is only a moment in a wider movement of thought. Thus, finite thinking, or ‘the understanding’ in Hegel’s terms, the mode of thought of Aristotle, is really just a single moment in a broader process called speculative reason. It is only by reifying specu- | lative thought that we end up with the problems we have encountered so far; that is, by denying that there is a greater moment to representation than finite representation, we find ourselves unable to explain the concept of totality.
(44-45)


Hegel’s infinite representation involves his notion of dialectic, which examines the development of concepts rather than seeing their senses as fixed.

Central to Hegel’s explanation of infinite representation is the notion of dialectic. Essentially, Hegel wants to argue that rather than the meanings of terms simply being given by definition, we find when we analyse the movement of thought thinking these terms that their meaning arises from the content itself.
(45)

[In his Science of Logic, Hegel shows this dialectical movement of concepts by tracing it to its origins in indeterminate being. See this entry on a text by Graham Priest for an explanation and quotation of the passages of the Hegel text. The idea is that even if we start with the most basic concept, indeterminate being, just by conceptualizing it, we obtain another concept, indeterminate nothing. Why? Well, try to think being in its purity, and with no reference to any beings, that is, with no determination whatsoever. What comes into your mind? Probably nothing comes into your mind. Voilà. The concept of nothing comes into your mind when you think the most basic concept, being. There is a dynamic built into this concept. Specifically we think indeterminate nothing, since we are not thinking some specific instance of nothingness or some particular negation of a being. But conceptually speaking, what is there to distinguish indeterminate being and indeterminate nothing in our minds? We conceive them as different notions. But each’s content is hard to unravel from the other’s, since both in a sense are empty of any determinate content. So, the first dynamic of thought is the production of opposition: being produces nothing, conceptually speaking. Next, there is a collapse of the two opposite concepts. So now see if this works for you. First conceive pure indeterminate being again, which should again bring to your mind the concept of pure indeterminate nothing. Now notice how they are individual and opposite concepts but are somehow difficult to pull apart on the basis of the conceptual content. The experience we are supposed to have now I am guessing is that we conceive the one rolling over into the other and that rolling back over into the first and so on. We think being, which makes us think nothing, which collapses back to being, which falls back to nothing, and so on. Their genetic pairing produces endless revolution. Voilà. We now have a third concept, arising from the mutual collapsing of the opposing first two, namely, we have the concept of pure becoming. Why? Because that is what happens in our mind when these concepts genetically produce and conflict with one another. The concepts are in a continual state of becoming their opposites. I have not studied the next step very well, but it might be something like this. At this point, we have the notion of becoming arising from the dynamic activity of the most basic ideas we can conceive. We have a dynamic unity of being and nothingness. But note that being at least in Aristotle is also understandable as ‘unity’. What do all beings share? They are all what they are. They are unified self-same things and they are not other to themselves (in this conception). Here now we have a unity (of being and nothing), so do we return to the indeterminate being of the first step? Perhaps we might consider indeterminate being also as indeterminate unity. But that is not what we have now at this stage of the dialectic movement. We specifically have the unity of being and nothing, and not the unity of anything whatsoever. So the concept of becoming leads to the notion of determinate unity, which is what? If something were determinate, we are dealing no longer with being in general but with some being in particular, and for that reason, perhaps the idea is that we are dealing with some existing thing. So the notion of determinate unity is also the notion of existence, perhaps. The concept of becoming (specifically of the becoming of being and nothing) gives rise to the concept of existence. I am not sure if becoming and existence are opposites and if they also dialectically sublate. But perhaps determinate existence is somehow incompatible with pure becoming, since pure becoming is more like a process of change, where determinate existence is something that may be lasting more than a timeless instant. At any rate, normally Hegel’s dialectic is thought to continue the same pattern, sometimes given the terms thesis, antithesis, and synthesis. The sublated third ‘category of thought’ (in our example ‘becoming’) will give rise to its opposite (which may be existence), and they will themselves produce yet another third category, and so on. The process supposedly ends with a final Absolute Idea (the Notion).]

Central to Hegel’s explanation of infinite representation is the notion of dialectic. Essentially, Hegel wants to argue that rather than the meanings of terms simply being given by definition, we find when we analyse the movement of thought thinking these terms that their meaning arises from the content itself. Hegel’s Science of Logic therefore traces the development of concepts from the simplest concept, that of pure, undifferentiated being, through to what he calls the Absolute Idea, or the Notion. By tracing the development of ideas themselves, we are able to see the inherent connections between them. Philosophy is therefore this movement of concepts themselves.
(45)

[The next part is very difficult for me to grasp. It seems we are saying the following. Normally we understand the infinite as what is not finite. But that is to limit the concept by saying what it is not. This means that the concept for the infinite is itself a finite concept. I am not sure why this is a problem. Do all concepts as concepts need to have the same properties as that which they are concepts of? Is the concept for red itself somehow a red concept? But it does help clarify what a finite representation is. Perhaps Hegel is interested not just in a representation of the infinite, but in an infinite representation. In other words, he wants something to have representational powers without being finitely limited like how Aristotelian representations are limited by definitional distinctions. I now must guess to the next notion here. Recall from our commentary above how when we think ‘being’ we thereby think its opposite ‘nothing’, which collapses back to being, and they keep revolving endlessly. This gives us the notion of becoming, but also, it is based on this ceaseless exchanging of opposites. The same could be happening when we think the concept of infinite. It is not the finite. We think the finite. It is not the infinite. They are co-definitional, and they keep exchanging one to the next over and over without end. This movement is perhaps part of the dialectical interactions of all opposites, but SH is only here discussing the pairing infinite/finite. This circle of revolution it seems is itself infinite, in that it has no beginning or end. Likewise, we might also think that if the absolute is a limit that comes after an infinite and not a finite progress, then the whole dialectic itself is infinite. I am not sure about that, since any ending would constitute a limit. At any rate, the very basic idea here seems to be that the dialectic is representational, because it generates the categories of understanding, by which we form judgments, and I think SH is saying judgments based on such categories are the form of representation. And also, in some important sense, perhaps the dynamics of this are endless and therefore infinite. So it is infinite representation. (I am still not sure why the ceaselessness of the movement is not understanding something by means of limits. Hegel speaks of its beginninglessness and endlessness. Are not beginnings and endings limits? They are not conceptual limits like a definition makes, but they still define the limits of a process or movement. And so, if something is ceaseless, since it is beginningless and endless, then we are defining its infinity by means of a negation of confining limits, that is, by saying that it has no end and no beginning and is in that way limitless.) Furthermore, we need to get to the idea that “Such a process involves seeing the infinite as essentially a contradictory structure – the identity of identity and difference” (SH 46). I am not sure how we get here yet. The simplest possibility I can think of is that somehow, perhaps later in the chain of categories, we arrive at identity which gives rise to its opposite difference. They collapse into one another, which would be like their identification with one another, and thus it would be the identification of identity and difference. The other way I can think of for getting to this notion would be is if even in a pairing like being and nothing we have an identification of identity and difference. I am not sure how. Perhaps the idea would be, it is the identity of indeterminate being, its meaning and its being just what it is conceptually, that gives rise to what is different from it. In other words, to be what one is, to have an identity, is also to differ from oneself. At any rate, the next idea is that the finite is in a perpetual process of vanishing or negation. I think this is simply the fact that any dialectical pairing would be a finite representation, but these dialectically give rise to others. So the finite representations always vanish, and this happens perpetually.]

For Hegel, therefore, the problems of finite representation emerge when we ignore this movement, and assume that concepts are just given. In this way, Hegel criticises his predecessors as follows [the following up to citation is Hegel quotation]:

Such presuppositions that infinity is different from finitude, that content is other than form, that the inner is other than the outer, also that mediation is not immediacy (as if anyone did not know such things), are brought forward by way of information and narrated and asserted rather than proved. (Hegel 1999: 41)

Finite representation therefore emerges for Hegel from the fact that we take for granted the nature of the distinction between the finite and the infinite. We presume that: ‘There are two worlds, one infinite and one finite, and in their relationship the infinite is only the limit of the finite and is thus only a determinate infinite, an infinite which is itself finite’ (Hegel 1999: 139–40). If we just view the infinite as a ‘beyond’ of the finite, and remain with finite thinking, however, we end up with an infinite which is itself limited, and hence is finite: ‘Owing to the inseparability of the infinite and the finite – or because this infinite remaining aloof on its own side is itself limited – there arises a limit; the infinite has vanished, and its other, the finite, has entered’ (Hegel 1999: 141). The heart of the difficulty is that the infinite is supposed to be that which is beyond limitation, but the basic structure of determining the infinite is by opposition, in other words by saying what the infinite is not. But by doing so, we introduce a limit into the notion of the infinite. Possessing a limit, however, is what defines finite things. For this reason, Hegel defines this understanding of the infinite as a ‘spurious infinite’ (Hegel 1999: 142). | We attempt to determine the infinite as a beyond, but in determining it, we limit it and make it finite. We thus have an infinite progression and alternation between finite and infinite terms. If we are truly to understand the infinite, and hence the finite, we need to see both as moments of one process [the following up to citation is Hegel quotation]:

The image of the progress to infinity is the straight line, at the two limits of which alone the infinite is, and always only is where the line – which is determinate being – is not, and which goes out beyond to this negation of its determinate being, that is, to the indeterminate; the image of true infinity, bent back into itself, becomes the circle, the line which has reached itself, which is closed and wholly present, without beginning and end. (Hegel 1999: 149)

The true infinite emerges when we step back from attempting to formulate the infinite through the progression, and recognise that the process of the circular movement of the finite into the infinite and back again is itself the infinite. Such a process involves seeing the infinite as essentially a contradictory structure – the identity of identity and difference. The finite is in a perpetual process of vanishing or negation, and this movement itself is seen as the infinite. Everything therefore falls under conceptual determination. Hegel’s claim is thus that it is only by moving to a different way of understanding concepts, namely speculative reason, that we are able to truly understand either of the categories of finitude or infinitude.
(SH 45-46)


[The next part is a bit hard for me to grasp. We will look at Deleuze’s criticism of Hegel’s infinite representation. We need to see how Hegel pushes difference past opposition to contradiction. I am not sure how this is so, since I would have assumed that anything in opposition is also in contradiction. Perhaps the difference is that opposing things do not necessarily negate one another (or imply the falsity of the other), but contradictory things do. Let us take the example of being and nothing. We can say they are opposed. But we are not necessarily saying just yet that they are in contradiction. So again, perhaps the difference is that opposition here means somehow being incompatible or non-identical in some problematic way, but contradiction implies additionally the negation of one by the other. Hegel takes oppositions but says they sublate negationally on account of their mutual contradictoriness. But I am not sure if I interpret this correctly. The next idea is that Hegel’s dialectical movement seems univocal since there is just one process that is generative of many categories; however, it really is not. I do not understand why yet. And I cannot understand why yet from the quotation in Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. It has something to do with the organization of a Form and the formation of subjects. I am not sure, but maybe the problem is that the dialectic is univocal but it is used to explain distinct subjectivities and maybe substances, and is therefore really somehow equivocal. I will quote:]

What, therefore, is the relationship between the infinite and finite that Hegel develops? Deleuze’s claim is that infinite representation is no better than finite representation. In distinguishing the two, he writes that ‘it treats identity as a pure infinite principle instead of treating it as a genus, and extends the rights of the concept to the whole instead of fixing their limits’ (DR 50/61). The finite and the infinite are still understood oppositionally, as each is not the other, but at the same time, they are united together, in that they are part of one process. Now, if two terms are opposed to each other, but are both asserted simultaneously, then we have a contradiction. This is why Deleuze claims (and Hegel would agree) that speculative reason operates by pushing difference past opposition to contradiction. In that everything is one element (the infinite), it appears as if we have a univocal theory much like Spinoza’s. In actual fact, however, Hegel’s theory preserves the central features of representation: ‘Goethe, and even Hegel in certain respects, have been considered Spinozists, but they are not really Spinozists, because they | never ceased to link the plan[e of infinite representation] to the organization of a Form and to the formation of a Subject’ (SPP 128–9).
(SH 46-47)


SH then explains that Deleuze offers three criticisms to Hegel’s approach. 1) Because Hegel uses language and words, he is using finite representations and thus never escapes finite representation. [The next point about the universal I have difficulty grasping. I am not sure what the universal has to do with Hegel’s dialectic, at least as the term is meant here. Perhaps the dialectic is universal because all things come about through it. Then we need to somehow add into this the concept of the singular, which is neither particular nor universal. It seems Kierkegaard’s Abraham is singular. Recall SH’s discussion of this. God’s command goes against the categorical imperative, which is a universalization of moral behavior. Let us work with the categorical  imperative first. We should not steal, because if everyone did, there would be no sense of property, and thus no stealing would be possible anyway. The prohibition against stealing then is universal. Any one instance of stealing or choosing not to steal is a particular instantiation of that universal. So actual acts relevant to stealing are particulars to the universal. But Abraham’s intent to kill his son is not relevant to the universal, since God’s command overrides the universal (the categorical imperative would say ‘never murder’). It is also not a particular, since it is not one of many common instances relative to the universal prohibition against murder. It is a unique and singular situation, given that God very uncharacteristically makes this cruel and illicit demand. So for this reason perhaps it is singular rather than particular. Even with this in mind, I am not quite sure I grasp the point here yet. Perhaps SH is saying that for Deleuze, to see every moment as part of a universal movement is to not notice its absolute uniqueness and singularity. Maybe the view is that newness is radically new. It comes out of nowhere. It is not implied or somehow otherwise contained in the prior moment. Each moment is not an instantiation of some greater pattern. Each moment is singular and unique unto itself. I will quote:]

Deleuze makes three main criticisms of this approach. First, ‘[Hegel] creates movement, even the movement of the infinite, but because he creates it with words and representations, nothing follows’ (DR 52/63). Deleuze’s claim is that Hegel has misunderstood the cause of the movement of thought by continuing to represent it, rather than seeing it as escaping representation. The aspect of representation which Deleuze takes to be critical here is the universal. ‘“Everyone” recognises the universal because it is itself the universal, but the profound sensitive conscience which is nevertheless presumed to bear the cost, the singular, does not recognise it’ (DR 52/63). The singular, or singularity, which is neither particular nor universal, is excluded by beginning with a term which is essentially universal. We can return to the figure of Abraham. Abraham cannot be understood within the framework of the universal, which is the precise reason for Kierkegaard’s introduction of him in Fear and Trembling.
(SH 47)


Now for the second criticism. 2) [I do not understand this one very well yet. It seems to be that Hegel’s dialectic never breaks from the genus-species model and thus still has the problems of Aristotle’s representational system. The way it keeps this Aristotelian model seems to be that all the movement revolves around a basic concept of the infinite as beginningless/endless ceaseless movement. It is not a definitional sort of structure. But it does seem to regard all particulars as instances of a common pattern or dynamic. The movement from being to nothing is of the same sort of movement as that from becoming to existence, and so in each and every other instance of the dialectic.]

The second criticism is that this movement is always around a particular point. Deleuze is claiming that Hegel relies on a ‘monocentring of circles’ (DR 49/60) which Deleuze claims comes about through Hegel’s adherence to the species–genus model. In the case of the finite and the infinite, movement ‘revolves’ around the central moment of the true infinite. Hegel has not got rid of the idea of a central identity, therefore.
(SH 47)


Now the third criticism. 3) Hegel’s basic structure of opposition is too crude to apply to the real world where there is much more ambiguity, overlap, mixing, and so on.

The third point, which relates the previous two, is that the idea of opposition, which Hegel uses to unite the particular and universal, is too rough to provide an adequate description of the world. ‘Oppositions are roughly cut from a delicate milieu of overlapping perspectives, of communicating distances, divergences and disparities, of heterogeneous potentials and intensities’ (DR 50/61). That is, Deleuze asserts that simply relying on a reinvigorated understanding of the distinction between finite and infinite will not provide the kinds of fine-grained distinctions needed to describe the world adequately.
(SH 47)

SH ends by noting that we cannot reduce Hegel to Aristotle despite their similarities. Hegel in many ways has responses to the problems of Aristotle’s system, but we do not need to review them for our purposes in this guide (47).

 

 

 

 

 

Citations from:

Somers-Hall, Henry. Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition. An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University, 2013.



Or if otherwise noted:


DR:
[Deleuze] Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York: Columbia University Press, 1994/London: Continuum, 2004.


 

SPP:

[Deleuze] Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, trans. Robert Hurley, San Francisco: City Lights Books, 1988.



Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1999), Science of Logic, trans. A. V. Miller, Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.

 





 

4 comments:

  1. I’d say for a start that while I’ve tried in general to explain the reasoning behind philosophical positions, here I could only give a broad outline – I’d suggest you turn to your own summary of my Hegel-Deleuze book to get a fuller picture of this (chapter 5 in particular)!

    *[The next part is very difficult for me to grasp. It seems we are saying the following. Normally we understand the infinite as what is not finite. But that is to limit the concept by saying what it is not. This means that the concept for the infinite is itself a finite concept. I am not sure why this is a problem. Do all concepts as concepts need to have the same properties as that which they are concepts of? Is the concept for red itself somehow a red concept?]

    A better way to understand this claim might be to ask, what to we mean by the infinite? Well, we mean that which is not finite. The difficulty is that here what makes the infinite meaningful is that we understand it as opposed to the finite. This implies, however, that rather than being unlimited, our understanding of the infinite sees it as limited by the finite. But being limited is precisely what defines the finite. So, if we begin with the finite, we try to define the infinite against it, but instead just get another finite term. If we repeat this procedure, we end up with an infinite sequence of finite terms – this is Hegel’s bad infinite. The good infinite for Hegel is neither the finite, nor the infinite (understood in these terms) but is rather the movement between the finite and the finite. Here’s a slightly longer account of the dialectic from my piece on the logic of the rhizome in Jim Vernon and Karen Houle’s collection on Hegel and Deleuze:


    The dialectic of infinity occurs in the first part of the Science of Logic, in the doctrine of Being. As Hegel’s dialectic proceeds immanently, we will begin at the stage where the dialectic has reached the notion of ‘something’. The notion of something which Hegel develops is perhaps the most basic which we could conceive of, merely that of the unity of a being and a quality. For Hegel, ‘something’ also contains a moment of self relation, in that as a unified concept, it is the negation of the difference between being and quality. As self-relating negation, however, we can see it as containing two moments. Whilst it is a determinate being, it is also the negation of this determinate being. It is something other than something: ‘the second is equally a determinate being, but determined as a negative of the something – an other.’ Something therefore contains two moments of being. It implies the existence of another. We should be able to see, however, that each of these moments, the something and the other, have the same structure. The labels, something and other, only apply to the extent that we began our analysis from one of these two entities. Each is therefore both a something, and an other to its other. We can reverse this understanding of each being a something, and recognise that each is also, in its own self, an other: ‘if of two things we call one A, and the other B, then in the first instance B is determined as the other. But A is just as much the other of B. Both are, in the same way, others.’ As such, we have a continual process of something becoming other than itself. As its nature is to be other than itself, however, this negation is a constant return into itself. That is, in the other negating itself, it becomes other to this other, a something.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Whilst something at first appeared to be a self contained moment, we can see now that it is in fact better characterised by this moment of openness to another. We should note that we now have an understanding as something being constituted by this relation to the other. Becoming other is a key feature of the structure of something, and to this extent, we can now see something as having a particular constitution. This aspect of constitution is double for something. It is constituted by relating to, and being distinct from, something other. In other words, it is this, rather than that. These two moments are the foundation of the distinction between being in itself and being for another, as it is both self-enclosed, but also other related. We can now ask how this essential relation to another plays out in the determination of something. If something is to be determined by its relations to another, it should be the case that at least two conditions must be met: first, it must form some kind of relation to this other, in order that determination can take place. Second, it must differ from the other, as without this difference, there is no other to determine it. These two conditions imply the need for a further concept, that of limit, which will both separate the two somethings, and yet as they share this limit, relate them. The limit circumscribes what a thing is by defining the point at which it transitions into its other. But as such, the limit has a paradoxical quality, as it is the ground for the existence of something (as something requires this relation and separation from another), but is also the point at which something is not. Something is what it is within its limit. Here we transition to another category, however. What is fundamental to the structure of something is its relation to its limit, but its limit is what it is not. This fundamental relationship towards its own negation leads us to recognise that at the heart of something is finitude.

    For finitude, therefore, limit is not merely something indifferent, but is rather a fundamental moment in its structure. Without this limit, finitude would become infinitude – it would go beyond itself. This is the first sense of the infinite, as a pure beyond. The limit therefore acts to prevent the finite from becoming something other than itself. As we cannot at this stage countenance the possibility of the finite containing the infinite, the notion of limit does not simply signify an arbitrary point in something’s relation to another something, but is also a limitation – that which prevents finitude from becoming infinite. This brings in a new moment into the concept of finitude. As finitude now contains this essential moment of limitation, we can say that it also brings in a notion that it ought to overcome this limitation. This ‘ought’ captures the complex structure of finitude. It contains both its being and its limitation. In fact, these two moments are in tension with one another. Finitude wants to transcend its limitation, but as the limitation is integral to finitude, it resists the force of the ought. As the moment of transcendence provided by the ought is integral to finitude, however, it does go beyond itself. These two moments do not collapse into a unity, however. Instead, we have a constant process of moving between the two moments. Finitude perishes because it transcends its limitation, but this perishing simply leads to the emergence of another moment of finitude, as the ought includes the moment of limitation within it. We have, therefore, a perpetual series of finite moments, the perishing of one leading to the generation of the next. This series of finite moments, however, is an infinite series.

    ReplyDelete
  3. When we look at the notion of the infinite, however, we can see that it relies on its reference to the finite. It is specified as the beyond which escapes from the limitation of finitude. A result of this, however, is that the notion of limitation is inherent to the concept of the infinite. For this reason, this notion of the infinite is characterised by Hegel as the bad infinite. The finite and the infinite are therefore in fact rather similar to each other. Both are defined by their common limitation, and each relies on the other to sustain itself. So each concept requires that the other concept be determinately understood in order that it may itself become determinate. While we want to be able to understand each category in its own terms, we find that each concept leads us to consider the other. This leads us, however, into another form of infinity, an infinite series which oscillates between these two terms, as each refers itself to the other in order to vouchsafe its own determinacy. What conclusion can we draw from this? Well, the concept of the infinite is now itself defined by a process which can never be completed. It is therefore itself defined in terms of an ought to be which is never achieved. The infinite itself, therefore, once again collapses back into the finite.

    There is thus an inherent unity between these two categories, although also a moment of difference between them, depending on the emphasis which we place on the terms themselves. The infinite is determined, in part, by its differentiation from the finite. As such, however, it is tied to the notion of a limit, and thus finitude. It is a finitised infinite. But the finite now has a definite structure. It is no longer defined in terms of its ought. As such, it is an infinitised finite. Rather than these two terms being considered as defined in their own terms, we now explicitly recognise that finitude as part of its structure has a reference to infinity, and the infinite likewise contains a reference to the finite. These references mean that regardless of which term we begin with, we are driven to the other. Rather than seeing these terms as existing in a series, as was the case with the bad infinite, however, now that we have explicitly recognised that they reciprocally determine one another, we can see them as forming a circle. Thus, from the very structure of the infinite series of finite somethings, we are led to the notion that finite and infinite are concepts which are mediated by one another. Neither can be determined independently of the other. Once we recognise this, we can note that the true infinite is this structure of movement of the finite and infinite as a whole.

    ReplyDelete
  4. *[And I cannot understand why yet from the quotation in Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. It has something to do with the organization of a Form and the formation of subjects.]

    Yes, the point is that while Spinoza thinks the infinite (as substance) intensively, as a field that gives rise to forms and structures of organization, Hegel’s conception of the infinite begins with form, and simply puts it into motion. As such, it infinitises representation, rather than explaining the genesis of representation (and form), as Spinoza does for Deleuze. This is the origin of Deleuze’s first criticism of Hegel – by beginning with representation, he takes what for Deleuze is a surface effect for the real movement.

    *[I do not understand this one very well yet. It seems to be that Hegel’s dialectic never breaks from the genus-species model and thus still has the problems of Aristotle’s representational system.]

    This once again is a complex criticism, but you can get some sense of it by looking at the Phenomenology of Spirit. There, Hegel shows how the categories of a subject become more and more complex as what is implicit within them is made explicit, and they become more adequate. What Hegel doesn’t explain is the origin of the subject itself. As such, as with Aristotle, Hegel explains the determinations or categories that are applied to a subject, but not the constitution or emergence of a subject itself.

    ReplyDelete