by Corry Shores
[Search Blog Here. Index-tags are found on the bottom of the left column.]
[Central Entry Directory]
[Logic & Semantics, Entry Directory]
[Vergauwen's Metalogical Theory of Reference, Entry Directory]
[Search Blog Here. Index-tags are found on the bottom of the left column.]
[Central Entry Directory]
[Logic & Semantics, Entry Directory]
[Vergauwen's Metalogical Theory of Reference, Entry Directory]
[The following is summary. Paragraph headings are my own.]
Roger Vergauwen
A Metalogical Theory of Reference: Realism and Essentialism in Semantics
Chapter 1.2 Primitive Reference and Satisfaction
Truth, for Tarski, is a metalanguage predicate over object language sentences. We should draw our truth definitions from a formal language L. For Tarski, a language contains a finite number of undefined or primitive predicates.
We will now consider a simple example language L. It contains two primitive predicates:
a) "is the moon" and
b) "is blue."
Now consider any predicate P and also consider the sentence
P refers to x.
In our truth-conditional semantics, we will take this sentence to mean
P is true of x.
Now suppose that P is the predicate "is the moon." We would then make the truth-conditional sentence:
"is the moon" refers to x if and only if x is the moon.
Or, perhaps P is the predicate "is blue." Hence
"is blue" refers to x if and only if x is blue.
Let's now place this in more general terms. We will speak of the simple language L along with its finite number of predicates:
P primitively refers to x if and only if
(a) P is the expression "is the moon" and x is the moon
(b) is the expression "is blue" and x is indeed blue.
We construct the non-primitive predicates using such things as truth functional connectors and quantifiers. We may define a primitive reference by giving a list such as the one above.
No comments:
Post a Comment